Phenomenology is the study of structures of consciousness as
experienced from the first-person point of view. The central structure of an
experience is its intentionality.
Phenomenology as a discipline is distinct from but related
to other key disciplines in philosophy, such as ontology, epistemology, logic,
and ethics.
Phenomenological issues of intentionality, consciousness,
qualia, and first-person perspective have been prominent in recent philosophy
of mind.
1. What is Phenomenology?
The discipline of phenomenology may be defined initially as
the study of structures of experience, or consciousness. Literally,
phenomenology is the study of “phenomena”: appearance of things, or things as
they appear in our experience, or the ways we experience things, thus the
meanings things have in our experience.
The historical movement of phenomenology is the
philosophical tradition launched in the first half of the 20th century
by Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Jean-Paul Sartre, et al.
Phenomenology as a discipline has been central to the
tradition of continental European philosophy throughout the 20th
century, while philosophy of mind has evolved in the Austro-Anglo-American
tradition of analytic philosophy that developed throughout the 20th
century.
Basically, phenomenology studies the structure of various
types of experience ranging from perception, thought, memory, imagination,
emotion, desire, and volition to bodily awareness, embodied action, and social
activity, including linguistic activity. The structure of these forms of
experience typically involves what Husserl called “intentionality”, that is,
the directedness of experience toward things in the world, the property of
consciousness that it is a consciousness of or about something. According to
classical Husserlian phenomenology, our experience is directed
toward—represents or “intends”—things only through
particular concepts, thoughts, ideas, images, etc. These make up the meaning or
content of a given experience, and are distinct from the things they present or
mean.
Thus, phenomenology leads from conscious experience into
conditions that help to give experience its intentionality. Traditional
phenomenology has focused on subjective, practical, and social conditions of
experience. Recent philosophy of mind, however, has focused especially on the
neural substrate of experience, on how conscious experience and mental
representation or intentionality are grounded in brain activity.
Cultural conditions thus seem closer to our experience and
to our familiar self-understanding than do the electrochemical workings of our
brain, much less our dependence on quantum-mechanical states of physical
systems to which we may belong.
2. The Discipline of Phenomenology
The discipline of phenomenology is defined by its domain of
study, its methods, and its main results.
Phenomenology studies structures of conscious experience as experienced from the first-person point of view, along with relevant conditions of experience. The central structure of an experience is its intentionality, the way it is directed through its content or meaning toward a certain object in the world.
Conscious experiences have a unique feature: we experience
them, we live through them or perform them. Other things in the world we may
observe and engage. But we do not experience them, in the sense of living
through or performing them. This experiential or first-person feature—that of
being experienced—is an essential part of the nature or structure of conscious
experience… This feature is both a phenomenological and an ontological feature
of each experience: it is part of what it is for the experience to be
experienced (phenomenological) and part of what it is for the experience to be
(ontological).
Importantly, also, it is type of experience that
phenomenology pursues, rather than a particular fleeting experience—unless its
type is what interest us.
What makes an experience conscious is a certain awareness
one has of the experience while living through or performing it… For
awareness-of-experience is a defining trait of conscious experience, the trait
that gives experience a first-person, lived character. It is that lived
character of experience that allows a first-person perspective on the object of
study, namely, experience, and that perspective is characteristic of the
methodology of phenomenology.
The overall form of the given sentence articulates the basic
form of intentionality in the experience: subject-act-content-object.
In this way, in the practice of phenomenology, we classify,
describe, interpret, and analyze structures of experiences in ways that answer
to our own experience.
Intentionality is thus the salient structure of our
experience, and much of phenomenology proceeds as the study of different
aspects of intentionality.
3. From Phenomena to Phenomenology
In its root meaning, then, phenomenology is the study of
phenomena: literally, appearances as opposed to reality. This ancient
distinction launched philosophy as we emerged from Plato’s cave. Yet the
discipline of phenomenology did not blossom until the 20th century
and remains poorly understood in many circles of contemporary philosophy.
Brentano distinguished descriptive
psychology from genetic psychology…
This thesis of intentional directedness was the hallmark of Bretano’s
descriptive psychology. In 1889 Bretano used the term “phenomenology” for
descriptive psychology, and the way was paved for Husserl’s new science of
phenomenology.
Phenomenology as we know it was launched by Edmund Husserl
in his Logical Investigations
(1900-01)… (Interestingly, both lines of research trace back to Aristotle, and
both reached importantly new results in Husserl’s day.)
So phenomena must be reconceived as objective intentional
contents (sometimes called intentional objects) of subjective acts of
consciousness.
These contents are shareable by different acts of
consciousness, and in that sense they are objective, ideal meanings… For
Husserl, phenomenology would study consciousness without reducing the objective
and shareable meanings that inhabit experience to merely subjective
happenstances. Ideal meaning would be the engine of intentionality in acts of
consciousness.
4. The History and Varieties of Phenomenology
The most famous of the classical phenomenologists were
Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, and Merleau-Ponty.
Husserl defined phenomenology as “the science of the essence
of consciousness”, centered on the defining trait of intentionality, approached
explicitly “in the first person”… How I see or conceptualize or understand the
object I am dealing with defines the meaning of that object in my current
experience. Thus, phenomenology features a study of meaning, in a wide sense
that includes more than what is expressed in language.
For Heidegger, we and our activities are always “in the
world”, our being is being-in-the-world, so we do not study our activities by
bracketing the world, rather we interpret our activities and the meaning things
have for us by looking to our contextual relations to things in the world.
Indeed, for Heidegger, phenomenology resolves into what he called “fundamental
ontology”… Heidegger resisted Husserl’s neo-Cartesian emphasis on consciousness
and subjectivity, including how perception presents things around us. By
contrast, Heidegger held that our more basic ways of relating to things are in
practical activities like hammering, where the phenomenology reveals our
situation in a context of equipment and in being-with-others.
Much of Being and Time
develops an existential interpretation of our modes of being including,
famously, our being-toward-death.
One of Heidegger’s most innovative ideas was his conception
of the “ground” of being, looking to modes of being more fundamental than the
things around us.
In Sartre’s model of intentionality, the central player in
consciousness is a phenomenon, and the occurrence of a phenomenon just is a
conscious-of-an-object. Indeed, all things in the world, as we normally
experience them, are phenomena, beneath or behind which lies their
“being-in-itself”. Consciousness, by contrast, has “being-for-itself”, since
each consciousness is not only a consciousness-of-its-object but also a
pre-reflective consciousness-of-itself (conscience de soi). Yet for Sartre,
unlike Husserl, the “I” or self is nothing but a sequence of acts of
consciousness, notably including radically free choices (like a Humean bundle
of preceptions).
Sartre’s phenomenology in Being and Nothingness became the philosophical foundation for his
popular philosophy of existentialism, sketched in his famous lecture
“Existentialism is a Humanism” (1945).
Through vivid description of the “look” of the Other, Sartre
laid groundwork for the contemporary political significance of the concept of
the Other.
In Phenomenology of
Perception (1945) Merleau-Ponty developed a rich variety of phenomenology
emphasizing the role of the body in human experience.
Merleau-Ponty focused on the “body image”, our experience of
our own body and its significance in our activities. Extending Husserl’s
account of the lived body (as opposed to the physical body), Merleau-Ponty
resisted the traditional Cartesian separation of mind and body. For the body
image is neither in the mental realm nor in the mechanical-physical realm.
Rather, my body is, as it were, me in my engaged action with things I perceive
including other people.
In short, consciousness is embodied (in the world), and
equally body is infused with consciousness (with cognition of the world).
5. Phenomenology and Ontology, Epistemology, Logic, Ethics
Historically, though, ethics has been on the horizon of
phenomenology… An explicitly phenomenological approach to ethics emerged in the
works of Emmanuel Levinas, a Lithuanian phenomenologist… In Totality and Infinity
(1961), modifying themes drawn from Husserl and Heidegger, Levinas focused on
the significance of the “face” of the other, explicitly developing grounds for
ethics in this range of phenomenology.
Still, political theory has remained on the borders of
phenomenology. Social theory, however, has been closer to phenomenology as
such… Aspects of French “poststructuralist” theory are sometimes interpreted as
broadly phenomenological.
Classical phenomenology, then, ties into certain areas of
epistemology, logic, and ontology, and leads into parts of ethical, social, and
political theory.
6. Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind
The tradition of analytic philosophy began, early in the 20th
century, with analyses of language, notably in the works of Gottlob Frege,
Bertrand Russell, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Then in The Concept of Mind (1949) Gilbert Ryle developed a series of
analyses of language about different mental states, including sensation,
belief, and will.
In short, phenomenology by any other name lies at the heart
of the contemporary mind-body problem.
But materialism does not fit comfortably with phenomenology.
For it is not obvious how conscious mental states as we experience
them—sensations, thoughts, emotions—can simply be the complex neural states that
somehow subserve or implement them.
The analysis of consciousness and intentionality is central
to phenomenology as appraised above, and Searle’s theory of intentionality
reads like a modernized version of Husserl’s… However, there is an important
difference in background theory. For Searle explicitly assumes the basic
worldview of natural science, holding that consciousness is part of nature. But
Husserl explicitly brackets that assumption, and later
phenomenologist—including Heidegger, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty—seem to seek a
certain sanctuary for phenomenology beyond the natural sciences. And yet
phenomenology itself should be largely neutral about further theories of how
experience arises, notably from brain activity.
The philosophy of mind may be factored into the following
disciplines or ranges of theory relevant to mind: Phenomenology, Neuroscience,
Cultural analysis, and Ontology of mind
7. Phenomenology in Contemporary Consciousness Theory
But now a problem remains. Intentionality essentially involves meaning, so the question arises how meaning appears in phenomenal character. Importantly, the content of a conscious experience typically carries a horizon of background meaning, meaning that is largely implicit rather than explicit in experience. But then a wide range of content carried by an experience would not have a consciously felt phenomenal character.
from Phenomenology: Stanford Encyclopedia Philosophy
댓글 없음:
댓글 쓰기