Systems in Context:
On the Outcome of the Habermas/Luhmann-Debate
by Poul Kjaer, Ancilla
Iuris (anci.ch) 2006:66-77
1. Introduction
In the 1970s, much of German social theoretical discourse
centered around the debate between Niklas Luhmann and Jurgen Habermas… The
central question in this debate was whether the idea of emancipation through
rational political steering – the core element in Enlightenment thinking, as
well as in German idealism – could still be considered as meaningful. Luhmann
argued that it could not. Habermas conversely advocated for a revitalization of
Enlightenment ideals and German idealism, to be achieved by development of an
‘updated’ theory of emancipation.
At a first glance, the debate ended with publication of
Habermas’ Theorie des kommunikativen
Handelns (1981) and Luhmann’s Soziale
Systemie (1984).
It is the argument of this article, however, that it remains
both possible and fruitful to articulate Habermas’ theoretical ambitions, as
they have developed since the publication of Theories des kommunikativen Handelns, using system theoretical
tools advanced by Luhmann from the publication of Soziale Systeme onwards.
This article advances eight hypotheses: 1. The central
difference between Habermas’ and Luhmann’s theoretical positions is reducible
to a difference in assessment of the time-consuming character of social
operations. 2. Habermas’ position is based on the concept of lifeworld; but
this concept lacks logical coherence. 3. The concept of reiteration, presented
by Luhmann as an alternative to the concept of lifeworld, is logically more
stringent. 4. Luhmann’s theoretical elaboration nonetheless failed to grasp the
importance of context for the constitution of social phenomena, sharply
reducing its strength. 5. This shortcoming can be traced to Luhmann’s attempt
to de-couple systems theory from the German idealist tradition – which he
executed via a sophisticated self-mystification strategy, which sought to
present system theory as a new theory, lacking connection to any existing
tradition of social thought. Foundational, in constructing this mythology was
the concept of paradox. 6. Removing this self-mystifying overlay, the social
theoretical toolbox assembled by Luhmann can be used to promote a radically
different world-perspective, lacking the kind of skepticism dominating the late
Luhmann’s systems theory, and which accords with the German idealist tradition
from which systems theory originally emerged. 7. Consequently, Luhmann’s and
Habermas’ legal theories can be viewed as owing a common basis in the German
idealist tradition, which provides a structural basis for their conversion. 8.
Such a conversion allows for an understanding of the two theories as
complementary, in so far as the late Habermas’ discourse theory becomes a
normative superstructure to Luhmann’s descriptive theory of the society.
2. Time
The difference between Luhmann and Habermas’ theoretical
constructions is a difference in time. The central importance of time in
Luhmann’s work manifests in his adoption of the mantra in George Spencer
Brown’s calculus of indication: “Draw a distinction”. The purpose of
introducing such a distinction is to produce a difference, because only a
difference between this and that makes possible the observation of this or that. According to Luhmann, the
drawing of a distinction is an operation that unfolds in time.
But introducing a distinction is only the first step. An
observer also needs to indicate one
side of the distinction in order to remain attached to the distinction. So,
Luhmann defines observation as the unity of distinction and indication… On the
basis of difference between distinction and indication, therefore, Luhmann
concludes that distinction-making operations are characterized by structural
simultaneousness and operative non-simultaneousness.
This difference between structural simultaneousness and
operative non-simultaneousness is central to Luhmann’s attempt to theorize the
relationship between systems and their surroundings. But beyond this, it is the
central element in the theory of autopoesis which Luhmann presented in Soziale Systeme, and which he later
coupled to his version of the calculus of indication… Consequently, it can be
concluded, it is not only according to the calculus of indication, but also
according to the theory of autopoesis, that social systems should be understood
as phenomena operating in their own time.
That systems operate in their own time has far reaching
consequences… In other words, any attempt to understand relations between system
as causal relations are doomed to fail.
The conceptualization of social phenomena as non-causal runs
through Luhmann’s work as a major theme from beginning to end.
In contrast to Luhmann’s emphasis on structural
simultaneousness and operative-non-simultaneousness of social operations,
Habermas argues that social operations are characterized by structural and operative simultaneousness.
Habermas’ approach derives from the notion of inter-subjectivity, which claims
“sprach- und handlungsfahigen Subjeckten” are constituted through their
relations to other subjects. Consequently, the existence of a plurality of
subjects must be regarded as a structural condition… Habermas agues, in other
words, that communicative acts can be understood as operations which, without
generating time, can establish accordance between two or more subjects’
perspective on the world.
3. Lifeworld
The lifeworld is defined as the context, composed of
culturally and linguistically organized patterns of interpretation, within
which the “sprach- und handlungsfahige Subjekte” find themselves. It is a
common ground… which make it possible for two or more subjects to constitute a
common understanding of the world on the basis of an already existing shared
interpretation of it.
Nevertheless, the lifeworld cannot just be a ground (Boden),
but must be also be a horizon, since the lifeworld is moving ahead at the same
pace as the observer. Consequently, the lifeworld must be understood as
constituted by the distinction between ground and horizon. According to
Luhmann, this concept of lifeworld… is based on a paradox. This is because the
lifeworld cannot be the firm ground where all observations and actions are
unfolded and, at the same time, an infinite horizon which simply is the WORLD:
it cannot be moveable, if it is firm and, if it is firm, it cannot be moveable. Consequently, Luhmann presents an alternative formulation of the problem,
replacing the metaphorical concepts of horizon and ground with a distinction
between familiarity and non-familiarity. Now familiarity represents the ground,
and non-familiarity the horizon, thereby avoiding the contradictions inherent
in the misleading opposition between the stationary and the moveable as found
in Husserl’s and Habermas’ concepts of lifeworld.
4. Reiteration
In principle… on every occasion one’s indication will be the
same. However, though one always indicates the same, the result is never the same! This is because
indication leads to condensation of the indicated. Every time an indication is
reiterated, the observer obtains an increased feeling of what is being
indicated. Reiteration attributes an additional value to the indicated, and it
is exactly this value which Luhmann defines as familiarity.
This attribution has radical consequences. According to
Luhmann, when one reiterates an operation, once the distinction
familiar/unfamiliar has already been established through an earlier operation,
then the crossing of a distinction, to indicate the other side, does not cancel
indication of the side which one is leaving… Consequently, one can – at any
time – embark on a journey into the unknown without giving up the known… We
never have to leave the familiar world. It remains our life-world: We never
cross the boundary: it remains a horizon that moves as we move. But we know in
a familiar way about the unfamiliar.
With this approach, Luhmann presents a logically coherent
and operative version of phenomenological concept of lifeworld.
5. Context dependency
Still, it is important to understand that incorporation of
Habermas’ notion of lifeworld in the system theoretical universe is not a
one-sided undertaking. The concept of lifeworld, to a great extent, is a Trojan
horse which, once inside the walls, can trigger a profound shift of focus
within system theory itself.
This impression could, however, have been avoided if Luhmann
had made the choice to systematically incorporate the system theoretical
concept of lifeworld when conducting his empirical investigations.
6. German Idealism
System theory’s lack of focus on the function of context is
not an isolated technical problem. On the contrary, it is a fundamental defect
that can be traced to Luhmann’s attempt to de-couple systems theory from the
German idealist tradition…. According to Kant, it is only possible to think the
color red through a simultaneous indication of the phenomena in relation to
which the color red stands. A thinking of the color red, therefore, includes a
thinking of the frame within which the color red is constituted.
So, whereas Luhmann erases the concept of context from the
calculus of indication, thereafter stating that distinctions are typically made
within a context and producing a vast number of empirical analyses where the
importance of context is downplayed as much as possible, Kant’s work is
characterized by greater coherence between the logical foundations and concrete
analysis of social phenomena.
7. Paradox
He argues, his theory is founded on the paradox which
results from his concept of observation… One can, therefore, distinguish
between a first order observer who focuses on what is observed, and a second
order observer who observes how the first order observer observes. The second
order observer can see what the first order observer cannot – the first order
observer’s observation. Yet this does not give the second order observer a
privileged position, since she cannot observe her own observation either. The
second order observer is therefore a first order observer herself when she is
being observed by another third order observer.
Since Luhmann defines a paradox as the unity of different
things, he is entitled to conclude that the true basis of systems theory is paradox,
not identity.
Hence, in denying the concept of identity as the basic
concept of systems theory, the Luhmann of the late 1980s and 1990s abandoned
not only identity, but also the concept of distinction as well. The later
Luhmann, in other words, exceeds the distinction between distinction and
identity, in order to base his theory on paradox.
8. Meaning
Luhmann claims that a concept of world is too general to
serve as a basis for any profound analysis of social phenomena… Luhmann instead
emphasizes the concept of meaning (Sinn): “we will certainly need a medium that is the same on both sides of the frame, on its inside and on its outside. I
propose to call this medium meaning”.
The latter concept, according to Luhmann, is “coextensive with the world”…
Luhmann’s rationale for avoiding the notion of world must therefore lie elsewhere…
The main purpose of distinguishing the concepts of world and meaning, in other
words, is to avoid associations with the Story of the Creation and other acts
of initiation.
More concretely, the function of the concept of meaning in
Luhmann is to achieve de-paradoxialization through a neutralization of the
asymmetry he was earlier forced to introduce into the calculus of indication,
in order to make it an operational social theoretical tool…
The concept of meaning, therefore, remains irreplaceable but
also crucial to the theory’s overall viability. While this, in principle, was
recognized by the late Luhmann, he never transformed the concept of meaning
into a useable tool for describing social phenomena. Instead, it was retained
as a general background notion, encompassing everything and therefore
signifying nothing.
9. Self-mystification
Luhmann developed a sophisticated self-mystification
strategy, devising a highly imaginative terminology to go with it. Indeed, so
successful was he in this strategy, that many present day system theoreticians
appear to believe that Luhmann himself was responsible for the basic concepts
of the systems theory. Consequently, many theoreticians also believe that systems
theory is not embedded in any existing tradition - a problematic view, given that most system
theoretical concepts derive almost directly from German idealism.
Failure to acknowledge this heritage is becoming a major
threat to the systems theory’s future utility as a tool for social theoretical
analysis. This is because, firstly, it has the consequence that many of Luhmann’s
disciples are only capable of defending systems theory from within, whereas
they require a language bestowing a capacity to argue outside its own frame;
secondly, because it provides a structural basis for theoretical fundamentalism,
visible, for example, in the attempt to elevate the calculus of indication to a
position where it supplies the basis of all other system theoretical concepts. Electing such a
strategy for further theoretical development, however, undermines one of the
strongest elements of system theory – namely, the stability its
non-reductionist version possesses as a
system, precisely because it is not based on any one element but on a whole
range.
On an alternative view systems theory represents a further
development of the German idealist tradition of Kant, Fichte and Hegel to
Husserl… In contrast to earlier forms, systems theory is an explicitly
post-ontological theory.
This genealogical endeavor would allow the theory’s
liberation from its own self-mystifying semantics without total rejection.
Then, Luhmann’s rich social theoretical toolbox can be reopened and its
contents applied to promote perspectives on society other than the variety of
societal skepticism advocated by the late Luhmann.
10. Convergence
If systems theory is “opened up”, as described above, it
becomes more compatible with other theories, and especially with the
theoretical complex resulting from Habermas’ reconstruction and renewal of
German idealist insights.
The move away from a discourse ethics, and to a discourse
theory (by Habermas), in other words, points towards replacement of the “old-European”
striving for totality on the basis of a concept of morality, with a functional
and pragmatic approach, seeking to develop and deploy tools that can ensure a
continued coordination of the ongoing reproduction of autonomous social systems. Consequently, the design of mechanisms enabling such coordination is reduced to
the legal task of developing relevant procedural rules and safeguards.
Such an undertaking can be supported by insights contained
in the system theoretical concepts of morality and critique.
Luhmann’s concept of morality makes it possible to question
his claim that the system theoretical concepts of lifeworld and meaning do not
provide a basis for critique of modern society… Luhmann himself also provides
concept that can be applied to achieve objectives set by Habermas.
11. Conclusion
None of Luhmann’s “translations” of Habermasian concepts…
are effectively deployed. Yet, these concepts need to be applied, and need to
achieve a fundamentally different status within systems theory, since they
could solve a number of its central flaws.
In sum, one outcome of the Habermas/Luhmann debate is that the late Habermas’ discourse theory can be regarded as a normative superstructure to Luhmann’s descriptive theory of society. But a second is that, beyond the tendency to the two theoretical complexes’ convergence, a complete fusion, through the development of a fully fledged “inter-systemic” and “critical” systems theory, could provide a viable basis for further theoretical development. Such a theory might provide an optimal frame for the continuing reformulation of legal theory.
댓글 없음:
댓글 쓰기